An Alphabetical Analysis
Volume 10 - Practical Truth - Page 238 of 277
INDEX
'This is perhaps the commonest fault of any, as we are apt to feel
satisfied if our definition covers the case we have in our immediate
view, and to omit to examine whether it does not also admit something
else of which we were not at the moment thinking' (Venn).
'A definition must not contain the name defined', says Jevons, for by
subjecting a term to definition we assume that it is not thoroughly
understood, and the repetition of the unknown term cannot therefore make it
known.
The following are examples of definitions faulty in this respect:
A noun is the name of anything.
Life is the sum of vital functions.
The fact that 'noun' and 'name', 'life' and 'vital' are essentially
identical is sufficient to render the definition valueless:
'A definition must not be negative where it can be affirmative'
(Jevons).
The importance of all this to the student of Scripture, the teacher and
preacher, requires we trust, no further emphasis.  Before any article of our
faith can be clearly believed by ourselves, or made known to others, it must
be thrown into the form of a proposition that either affirms or denies some
attribute of the subject.  How can we affirm or deny if we use our terms
loosely?  What an incentive, therefore, to go to the Scriptures and seek true
definitions that shall be neither too wide nor too narrow; that shall be
reciprocal, grammatical and unambiguous.  Surely every reader will feel a
desire to be able thus to complete the following affirmation: God is ...
Faith is ...  Sin is ...  Justification is ...  Sanctification is ...  etc.
To do this is to have taken a great step toward that understanding which
Scripture itself places so highly.
Propositions
We have now run over the chief elements that go to compose a
proposition.  Logic, strictly speaking, is occupied with proof, not
assertion, but in our consideration we are free to bring forward any and all
aspects of the question as to what constitutes a valid argument.  Many a time
the error does not lie in the mode of reasoning, but in the proposition
itself and, therefore, before proceeding to give some idea of the syllogism,
and its use in arriving at a 'proof', we will bring together in this study
one or two somewhat axiomatic notes concerning assertions or propositions.
An assertion has reference to facts contained in a proposition.  A
proof discriminates between true and false propositions.  Assertion,
moreover, cannot be separated from the kindred study of the meaning of words,
definition, and the like:
'Every proposition asserts that some given subject does or does not
possess some attribute, or that some attribute is or is not (either in
all, or in some portion, of the subject in which it is met with)
conjoined with some other attribute'.